Mental Models are not just Mental Simulations

 

Champ's Mental Model of Expert /Novice

Champ's Mental Model of Expert /Novice

Ask your average learning theorist (Ha!  What’s that?) what a mental model is, and they will most likely describe it as an internal visualization that a learner can mentally “run” in order to understand, or predict.  Key word: visualization.  For example, components of a cell can be visualized, with chemicals crossing through a bi-lipid membrane, or, an excited atom is visualized with electrons jumping to the outer “shells”.  But I argue two points:

  1. mental models are not limited to the visualization of matter in action (i.e., simulations) and,
  2. mental models are structures of relationships, suggesting that “relationships” be a fourth ontology in Chi’s (1994) epistemological supposition (a topic for another paper all together!).


Norman (1983), in Gentner and Stevens’ (1983)  foundational book titled Mental Models, describes mental models as such:  “[i]n interacting with the environment, with others, and with the artifacts of technology, people form internal, mental models of themselves and of the things with which they are interacting. These models provide predictive and explanatory power for understanding the interaction” (p. 7).   A mental model is a conception or an understanding then, and is similar to Piaget’s  schema(1964), or Chi’s ontologies (1994).  Indeed, throughout Clement & Rea-Ramirez’ (2008) book, Model Based Learning and  Instruction in Science, the term “mental model” is often used synonymously with “conception”, especially in regard to novice  conceptions in comparison to scientific conceptions.  For example:

“A target model (IMTS) is a mental model that students can effectively use to explain real life situations and one that is more scientifically correct than their initial models…” (Rea-Ramirez, 2008, pg. 50).

Literature defining mental models has been contradicting and controversial.  Much of the confusion regarding the definition of mental models is due to the fact that empirical studies of mental models are easiest when carried out within technical domains like physics, and thus, research is selective in which type of mental models is studied.  That is, it is easier to communicate and assess a mental model that describes a learner’s visual or spatial understandings of objects in the physical world, like, how motion of an object can imply force (Clement, 1983), or mental models of electricity as flowing waters or teeming crowds (Gentner & Gentner, 1983).  These “misconception” or “preconception” studies, when viewed through Chi’s (1994) theory of incompatibility, illustrate conceptual change as a learner reassigns a concept from the ontological category of matter, to the ontological process category of  constraint-based interactions.  Matter can be seen, touched, measured.  Constraint-based interactions like force and electricity have no beginning or end, they are processes with fuzzy boundaries.  Stevens & Gentner (1983) even advise that researchers stay with what is easily measurable; they should  “choose domains for which there exists some normative knowledge that is relatively easy to detail explicitly…[t]he reason that mental models research has focused on seemingly technical domains is precisely because those domains that have proved to be the most tractable to physical scientists are the ones for which there exists the best explicit normative models” (p. 2).   As an example, Stevens & Gentner explain that it is easier to describe novice and expert differences in mental models of physical worlds than something as abstract as interpersonal relations in a domain such as marriage.  Levels of difficulty in research, however, do not discount the existence of mental models within those subjective or ethereal domains, domains that are more difficult to visualize.

3 thoughts on “Mental Models are not just Mental Simulations

  1. In my experience in instructional design, it is very useful to think of a mental model as a heuristic representation of an expert’s epistemology, rather than a representation of a reality per se. Thinking about it as a heuristic sidesteps the question of the normative or absolute nature of the content, and focuses on the utility of the heuristic as a guide to practice. It is not intended to be absolute – rather, it is a kind of an 80-20 representation of the algorithms in terms of which experts know, think, decide, and act. I think of mental models as ‘epistemologies’ in the Batesonian sense – Bateson described epistemology as the set of rules whereby an organism ‘knows, thinks, and decides. More and more what we find is that knowledge is not useful in instruction – epistemology, however, is extremely so.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s